by
David Pratt
Reprinted with permission from Journal of Scientific Exploration,
11:1, pp. 69-78, Spring 1997
Journal of Scientific Exploration
JSE Homepage
Abstract
Quantum theory is open to different interpretations, and
this paper reviews some of the points of contention. The standard
interpretation of quantum physics assumes that the quantum world is
characterized by absolute indeterminism and that quantum systems
exist objectively only when they are being measured or observed.
David Bohm’s ontological interpretation of quantum theory
rejects
both these assumptions. Bohm’s theory that quantum events are party
determined by subtler forces operating at deeper levels of reality
ties in with John Eccles’ theory that our minds exist outside the
material world and interact with our brains at the quantum level.
Paranormal phenomena indicate that our minds can communicate with
other minds and affect distant physical systems by nonordinary
means. Whether such phenomena can be adequately explained in terms
of nonlocality and the quantum vacuum or whether they involve
superphysical forces and states of matter as yet unknown to science
is still an open question, and one which merits further experimental
study.
Introduction
Quantum theory is generally regarded as one of the most successful
scientific theories ever formulated. But while the mathematical
description of the quantum world allows the probabilities of
experimental results to be calculated with a high degree of
accuracy, there is no consensus on what it means in conceptual
terms. Some of the issues involved are explored below.
Quantum uncertainty
According to the uncertainty principle, the position and momentum of
a subatomic particle cannot be measured simultaneously with an
accuracy greater than that set by Planck’s constant. This is because
in any measurement a particle must interact with at least one
photon, or quantum of energy, which acts both like a particle and
like a wave, and disturbs it in an unpredictable and uncontrollable
manner. An accurate measurement of the position of an orbiting
electron by means of a microscope, for example, requires the use of
light of short wavelengths, with the result that a large but
unpredictable momentum is transferred to the electron. An accurate
measurement of the electron’s momentum, on the other hand, requires
light quanta of very low momentum (and therefore long wavelength),
which leads to a large angle of diffraction in the lens and a poor
definition of the position.
According to the conventional interpretation of quantum physics,
however, not only is it impossible for us to measure a particle’s
position and momentum simultaneously with equal precision, a
particle does not possess well-defined properties when it is not
interacting with a measuring instrument. Furthermore, the
uncertainty principle implies that a particle can never be at rest,
but is subject to constant fluctuations even when no measurement is
taking place, and these fluctuations are assumed to have no causes
at all. In other words, the quantum world is believed to be
characterized by absolute indeterminism, intrinsic ambiguity, and
irreducible lawlessness. As the late physicist David Bohm (1984, p.
87) put it:
"it is assumed that in any particular experiment, the
precise result that will be obtained is completely arbitrary in the
sense that it has no relationship whatever to anything else that
exists in the world or that ever has existed."
Bohm (ibid., p. 95) took the view that the abandonment of causality
had been too hasty:
"it is quite possible that while the quantum
theory, and with it the indeterminacy principle, are valid to a very
high degree of approximation in a certain domain, they both cease to
have relevance in new domains below that in which the current theory
is applicable. Thus, the conclusion that there is no deeper level of
causally determined motion is just a piece of circular reasoning,
since it will follow only if we assume beforehand that no such level
exists."
Most physicists, however, are content to accept the
assumption of absolute chance. We shall return to this issue later
in connection with free will.
Collapsing the wave function
A quantum system is represented mathematically by a wave function,
which is derived from Schrödinger’s equation. The wave function can
be used to calculate the probability of finding a particle at any
particular point in space. When a measurement is made, the particle
is of course found in only one place, but if the wave function is
assumed to provide a complete and literal description of the state
of a quantum system -- as it is in the conventional interpretation
-- it would mean that in between measurements the particle dissolves
into a "superposition of probability waves" and is potentially
present in many different places at once. Then, when the next
measurement is made, this wave packet is supposed to instantaneously
"collapse," in some random and mysterious manner, into a localized
particle again. This sudden and discontinuous "collapse" violates
the Schrödinger equation, and is not further explained in the
conventional interpretation.
Since the measuring device that is supposed to collapse a particle’s
wave function is itself made up of subatomic particles, it seems
that its own wave function would have to be collapsed by another
measuring device (which might be the eye and brain of a human
observer), which would in turn need to be collapsed by a further
measuring device, and so on, leading to an infinite regress. In
fact, the standard interpretation of quantum theory implies that all
the macroscopic objects we see around us exist in an objective,
unambiguous state only when they are being measured or observed.
Schrödinger devised a famous thought-experiment to expose the absurd
implications of this interpretation. A cat is placed in a box
containing a radioactive substance, so that there is a fifty-fifty
chance of an atom decaying in one hour. If an atom decays, it
triggers the release of a poison gas, which kills the cat. After one
hour the cat is supposedly both dead and alive (and everything in
between) until someone opens the box and instantly collapses its
wave function into a dead or alive cat.
Various solutions to the "measurement problem" associated with
wave-function collapse have been proposed. Some physicists maintain
that the classical or macro-world does not suffer from quantum
ambiguity because it can store information and is subject to an
"arrow of time", whereas the quantum or micro-world is alleged to be
unable to store information and time-reversible (Pagels, 1983). A
more extravagant approach is the many-worlds hypothesis, which
claims that the universe splits each time a measurement (or
measurement-like interaction) takes place, so that all the
possibilities represented by the wave function (e.g. a dead cat and
a living cat) exist objectively but in different universes. Our own
consciousness, too, is supposed to be constantly splitting into
different selves, which inhabit these proliferating,
non-communicating worlds.
Other theorists speculate that it is consciousness that collapses
the wave function and thereby creates reality. In this view, a
subatomic particle does not assume definite properties when it
interacts with a measuring device, but only when the reading of the
measuring device is registered in the mind of an observer (which may
of course be long after the measurement has taken place). According
to the most extreme, anthropocentric version of this theory, only
selfconscious beings such as ourselves can collapse wave functions.
This means that the whole universe must have existed originally as "potentia"
in some transcendental realm of quantum probabilities until
selfconscious beings evolved and collapsed themselves and the rest
of their branch of reality into the material world, and that objects
remain in a state of actuality only so long as they are being
observed by humans (Goswami, 1993). Other theorists, however,
believe that nonselfconscious entities, including cats and possibly
even electrons, may be able to collapse their own wave functions
(Herbert, 1993).
The theory of wave-function collapse (or state-vector collapse, as
it is sometimes called) raises the question of how the "probability
waves" that the wave function is thought to represent can collapse
into a particle if they are no more than abstract mathematical
constructs. Since the very idea of wave packets spreading out and
collapsing is not based on hard experimental evidence but only on a
particular interpretation of the wave equation, it is worth taking a
look at one of the main alternative interpretations, that of David Bohm and his associates, which provides an intelligible account of
what may be taking place at the quantum level.
The implicate order
Bohm’s ontological interpretation of quantum physics rejects the
assumption that the wave function gives the most complete
description of reality possible, and thereby avoids the need to
introduce the ill-defined and unsatisfactory notion of wave-function
collapse (and all the paradoxes that go with it). Instead, it
assumes the real existence of particles and fields: particles have a
complex inner structure and are always accompanied by a quantum wave
field; they are acted upon not only by classical electromagnetic
forces but also by a subtler force, the quantum potential,
determined by their quantum field, which obeys Schrödinger’s
equation. (Bohm & Hiley, 1993; Bohm & Peat, 1989; Hiley & Peat,
1991)
The quantum potential carries information from the whole environment
and provides direct, nonlocal connections between quantum systems.
It guides particles in the same way that radio waves guide a ship on
automatic pilot -- not by its intensity but by its form. It is
extremely sensitive and complex, so that particle trajectories
appear chaotic. It corresponds to what Bohm calls the implicate
order, which can be thought of as a vast ocean of energy on which
the physical, or explicate, world is just a ripple. Bohm points out
that the existence of an energy pool of this kind is recognized, but
given little consideration, by standard quantum theory, which
postulates a universal quantum field -- the quantum vacuum or
zero-point field -- underlying the material world. Very little is
known about the quantum vacuum at present, but its energy density is
estimated to be an astronomical 10^108 J/cm³ (Forward, 1996, pp.
328-37).
In his treatment of quantum field theory, Bohm proposes that the
quantum field (the implicate order) is subject to the formative and
organizing influence of a superquantum potential, which expresses
the activity of a superimplicate order. The superquantum potential
causes waves to converge and diverge again and again, producing a
kind of average particle-like behavior. The apparently separate forms
that we see around us are therefore only relatively stable and
independent patterns, generated and sustained by a ceaseless
underlying movement of enfoldment and unfoldment, with particles
constantly dissolving into the implicate order and then
recrystallizing. This process takes place incessantly, and with
incredible rapidity, and is not dependent upon a measurement being
made.
In Bohm’s model, then, the quantum world exists even when it is not
being observed and measured. He rejects the positivist view that
something that cannot be measured or known precisely cannot be said
to exist. In other words, he does not confuse epistemology with
ontology, the map with the territory. For Bohm, the probabilities
calculated from the wave function indicate the chances of a particle
being at different positions regardless of whether a measurement is
made, whereas in the conventional interpretation they indicate the
chances of a particle coming into existence at different positions
when a measurement is made. The universe is constantly defining
itself through its ceaseless interactions -- of which measurement is
only a particular instance -- and absurd situations such as
dead-and-alive cats therefore cannot arise.
Thus, although Bohm rejects the view that human consciousness brings
quantum systems into existence, and does not believe that our minds
normally have a significant effect on the outcome of a measurement
(except in the sense that we choose the experimental setup), his
interpretation opens the way for the operation of deeper, subtler,
more mindlike levels of reality. He argues that consciousness is
rooted deep in the implicate order, and is therefore present to some
degree in all material forms. He suggests that there may be an
infinite series of implicate orders, each having both a matter
aspect and a consciousness aspect:
"everything material is also
mental and everything mental is also material, but there are many
more infinitely subtle levels of matter than we are aware of"
(Weber, 1990, p. 151).
The concept of the implicate domain could be
seen as an extended form of materialism, but, he says,
"it could
equally well be called idealism, spirit, consciousness. The
separation of the two -- matter and spirit -- is an abstraction. The
ground is always one."
(Weber, 1990, p. 101)
Mind and free will
Quantum indeterminism is clearly open to interpretation: it either
means hidden (to us) causes, or a complete absence of causes. The
position that some events "just happen" for no reason at all is
impossible to prove, for our inability to identify a cause does not
necessarily mean that there is no cause. The notion of absolute
chance implies that quantum systems can act absolutely
spontaneously, totally isolated from, and uninfluenced by, anything
else in the universe. The opposing standpoint is that all systems
are continuously participating in an intricate network of causal
interactions and interconnections at many different levels.
Individual quantum systems certainly behave unpredictably, but if
they were not subject to any causal factors whatsoever, it would be
difficult to understand why their collective behavior displays
statistical regularities.
The position that everything has a cause, or rather many causes,
does not necessarily imply that all events, including our own acts
and choices, are rigidly predetermined by purely physical processes
-- a standpoint sometimes called "hard determinism" (Thornton,
1989). The indeterminism at the quantum level provides an opening
for creativity and free will. But if this indeterminism is
interpreted to mean absolute chance, it would mean that our choices
and actions just "pop up" in a totally random and arbitrary way, in
which case they could hardly be said to be our choices and the
expression of our own free will. Alternatively, quantum
indeterminism could be interpreted as causation from subtler,
nonphysical levels, so that our acts of free will are caused -- but
by our own selfconscious minds. From this point of view -- sometimes
called "soft determinism" -- free will involves active, selfconscious self-determination.
According to orthodox scientific materialism, mental states are
identical with brain states; our thoughts and feelings, and our
sense of self, are generated by electrochemical activity in the
brain. This would mean either that one part of the brain activates
another part, which then activates another part, etc., or that a
particular region of the brain is activated spontaneously, without
any cause, and it is hard to see how either alternative would
provide a basis for a conscious self and free will. Francis Crick
(1994), for example, who believes that consciousness is basically a
pack of neurons, says that the main seat of free will is probably in
or near a part of the cerebral cortex known as the anterior cingulate sulcus, but he implies that our feeling of being free is
largely, if not entirely, an illusion.
Those who reduce consciousness to a by-product of the brain disagree
on the relevance of the quantum-mechanical aspects of neural
networks: for example, Francis Crick, the late Roger Sperry (1994),
and Daniel Dennett (1991) tend to ignore quantum physics, while
Stuart Hameroff (1994) believes that consciousness arises from
quantum coherence in microtubules within the brain’s neurons. Some
researchers see a connection between consciousness and the quantum
vacuum: for example, Charles Laughlin (1996) argues that the neural
structures that mediate consciousness may interact nonlocally with
the vacuum (or quantum sea), while Edgar Mitchell (1996) believes
that both matter and consciousness arise out of the energy potential
of the vacuum.
Neuroscientist Sir John Eccles dismisses the materialistic
standpoint as a "superstition", and advocates dualist interactionism:
he argues that there is a mental world in addition to the material
world, and that our mind or self acts on the brain (particularly the
supplementary motor area of the neocortex) at the quantum level by
increasing the probability of the firing of selected neurons
(Eccles, 1994; Giroldini, 1991). He argues that the mind
is not only
nonphysical but absolutely nonmaterial and nonsubstantial. However,
if it were not associated with any form of energy-substance
whatsoever, it would be a pure abstraction and therefore unable to
exert any influence on the physical world. This objection also
applies to antireductionists who shun the word "dualist" and
describe matter and consciousness as complementary or dyadic aspects
of reality, yet deny consciousness any energetic or substantial
nature, thereby implying that it is fundamentally different from
matter and in fact a mere abstraction.
An alternative position is that which is echoed in many mystical and
spiritual traditions: that physical matter is just one "octave" in
an infinite spectrum of matter-energy, or consciousness-substance,
and that just as the physical world is largely organized and
coordinated by inner worlds (astral, mental, and spiritual), so the
physical body is largely energized and controlled by subtler bodies
or energy-fields, including an astral model-body and a mind or soul
(see Purucker, 1973). According to this view, nature in general, and
all the entities that compose it, are formed and organized mainly
from within outwards, from deeper levels of their constitution. This
inner guidance is sometimes automatic and passive, giving rise to
our automatic bodily functions and habitual and instinctual
behavior, and to the regular, lawlike operations of nature in
general, and sometimes it is active and self-conscious, as in our
acts of intention and volition. A physical system subjected to such
subtler influences is not so much acted upon from without as guided
from within. As well as influencing our own brains and bodies, our
minds also appear to be able to affect other minds and bodies and
other physical objects at a distance, as seen in paranormal
phenomena.
EPR and ESP
It was David Bohm and one of his supporters, John Bell of
CERN, who
laid most of the theoretical groundwork for the EPR experiments
performed by Alain Aspect in 1982 (the original thought-experiment
was proposed by Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen in 1935). These
experiments demonstrated that if two quantum systems interact and
then move apart, their behavior is correlated in a way that cannot
be explained in terms of signals traveling between them at or slower
than the speed of light. This phenomenon is known as nonlocality,
and is open to two main interpretations:
-
either it involves
unmediated, instantaneous action at a distance
-
or it involves
faster-than-light signaling
If nonlocal correlations are literally instantaneous, they would
effectively be noncausal; if two events occur absolutely
simultaneously, "cause" and "effect" would be indistinguishable, and
one of the events could not be said to cause the other through the
transfer of force or energy, for no such transfer could take place
infinitely fast. There would therefore be no causal transmission
mechanism to be explained, and any investigations would be confined
to the conditions that allow correlated events to occur at different
places.
It is interesting to note that light and other electromagnetic
effects were also once thought to be transmitted instantaneously,
until observational evidence proved otherwise. The hypothesis that
nonlocal connections are absolutely instantaneous is impossible to
verify, as it would require two perfectly simultaneous measurements,
which would demand an infinite degree of accuracy. However, as David Bohm and
Basil Hiley (1993, pp. 293-4, 347) have pointed out, it
could be experimentally falsified. For if nonlocal
connections are
propagated not at infinite speeds but at speeds greater than that of
light through a "quantum ether" -- a subquantum domain where current
quantum theory and relativity theory break down -- then the
correlations predicted by quantum theory would vanish if
measurements were made in periods shorter than those required for
the transmission of quantum connections between particles. Such
experiments are beyond the capabilities of present technology but
might be possible in the future. If superluminal interactions exist,
they would be "nonlocal" only in the sense of nonphysical.
Nonlocality has been invoked as an explanation for telepathy and
clairvoyance, though some investigators believe that they might
involve a deeper level of nonlocality, or what Bohm calls "super-nonlocality"
(similar perhaps to
Sheldrake’s "morphic resonance" (1989)). As
already pointed out, if nonlocality is interpreted to mean
instantaneous connectedness, it would imply that information could
be "received" at a distance at exactly the same moment as it is
generated, without undergoing any form of transmission. At most, one
could then try to understand the conditions that allow the instant
appearance of information.
The alternative position is that information -- which is basically a
pattern of energy -- always takes time to travel from its source to
another location, that information is stored at some paraphysical
level, and that we can access this information, or exchange
information with other minds, if the necessary conditions of
"sympathetic resonance" exist. As with
EPR, the hypothesis that
telepathy is absolutely instantaneous is unprovable, but it might be
possible to devise experiments that could falsify it. For if ESP
phenomena do involve subtler forms of energy traveling at finite but
perhaps superluminal speeds through superphysical realms, it might
be possible to detect a delay between transmission and reception,
and also some weakening of the effect over very long distances,
though it is already evident that any attenuation must be far less
than that experienced by electromagnetic energy, which is subject to
the inverse-square law.
As for precognition, the third main category of ESP, one possible
explanation is that it involves direct, "nonlocal" access to the
actual future. Alternatively, it may involve clairvoyant perception
of a probable future scenario that is beginning to take shape on the
basis of current tendencies and intentions, in accordance with the
traditional idea that coming events cast their shadows before them.
Bohm says that such foreshadowing takes place "deep in the implicate
order" (Talbot, 1992, p. 212) -- which some mystical traditions
would call the astral or akashic realms.
Psychokinesis and the unseen world
Micro-psychokinesis involves the influence of consciousness on
atomic particles. In certain micro-PK experiments conducted by
Helmut Schmidt, groups of subjects were typically able to alter the
probabilities of quantum events from 50% to between 51 and 52%, and
a few individuals managed over 54% (Broughton, 1991, p. 177).
Experiments at the PEAR lab at Princeton University have yielded a
smaller shift of 1 part in 10,000 (Jahn & Dunne, 1987). Some
researchers have invoked the theory of the collapse of wave
functions by consciousness in order to explain such effects. It is
argued that in micro-PK, in contrast to ordinary perception, the
observing subject helps to specify what the outcome of the collapse
of the wave function will be, perhaps by some sort of informational
process (Broughton, 1991, pp. 177-81). Eccles follows a similar
approach in explaining how our minds act on our own brains. However,
the concept of wave-function collapse is not essential to explaining
mind-matter interaction. We could equally well adopt the standpoint
that subatomic particles are ceaselessly flickering into and out of
physical existence, and that the outcome of the process is
modifiable by our will -- a psychic force.
Macro-PK involves the movement of stable, normally unmoving objects
by mental effort. Related phenomena include poltergeist activity,
materializations and dematerializations, teleportation, and
levitation. Although an impressive amount of evidence for such
phenomena has been gathered by investigators over the past one
hundred and fifty years (Inglis, 1984, 1992; Milton, 1994),
macro-PK
is a taboo area, and attracts little interest, despite -- or perhaps
because of -- its potential to overthrow the current materialistic
paradigm and revolutionize science. Such phenomena clearly involve
far more than altering the probabilistic behavior of atomic
particles, and could be regarded as evidence for forces, states of
matter, and nonphysical living entities currently unknown to
science. Confirmation that such things exist would provide a further
indication that within the all-embracing unity of nature there is
endless diversity.
The possible existence of subtler planes interpenetrating the
physical plane is at any rate open to investigation (see Tiller,
1993), and this is more than can be said for the hypothetical extra
dimensions postulated by superstring theory, which are said to be
curled up in an area a billion-trillion-trillionth of a centimeter
across and therefore completely inaccessible, or the hypothetical
"baby universes" and "bubble universes" postulated by some
cosmologists, which are said to exist in some equally inaccessible
"dimension".
The hypothesis of superphysical realms does not seem to be favored
by many researchers. Edgar Mitchell (1996), for example, believes
that all psychic phenomena involve nonlocal resonance between the
brain and the quantum vacuum, and consequent access to holographic,
nonlocal information. In his view, this hypothesis could explain not
only PK and ESP, but also out-of-body and near-death experiences,
visions and apparitions, and evidence usually cited in favor of a
reincarnating soul. He admits that this theory is speculative, unvalidated, and
may require new physics.
Further experimental studies of consciousness-related phenomena,
both normal and paranormal, will hopefully allow the merits of the
various contending theories to be tested. Such investigations could
deepen our knowledge of the workings of both the quantum realm and
our minds, and the relationship between them, and indicate whether
the quantum vacuum really is the bottom level of all existence, or
whether there are deeper realms of nature waiting to be explored.
References
-
Bohm, D. (1984). Causality and Chance in Modern Physics. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul. First published in 1957.
-
Bohm, D. & Hiley, B.J. (1993). The Undivided Universe: An
ontological interpretation of quantum theory. London and New York:
Routledge.
-
Bohm, D. & Peat, F.D. (1989). Science, Order & Creativity. London:
Routledge.
-
Broughton, R.S. (1991). Parapsychology: The Controversial Science.
New York: Ballantine Books.
-
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis: The Scientific Search
for the Soul. London: Simon & Schuster.
-
Dennett, D.C. (1991). Consciousness Explained. London: Allen
Lane/Penguin.
-
Eccles, J.C. (1994). How the Self Controls Its Brain. Berlin:
Springer-Verlag.
-
Forward, R.L. (1996). Mass Modification Experiment Definition Study,
Journal of Scientific Exploration, 10:3, 325.
-
Giroldini, W. (1991). Eccles’s Model of Mind-Brain Interaction and Psychokinesis: A Preliminary Study, Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 5:2, pp. 145-61.
-
Goswami, A. with Reed, R.E. & Goswami, M. (1993). The Self-Aware
Universe: How consciousness creates the material world. New York:
Tarcher/Putnam.
-
Hameroff, S.R. (1994). Quantum coherence in microtubules: A neural
basis for emergent consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies,
1:1, 91.
-
Herbert, N. (1993). Elemental Mind: Human Consciousness and the New
Physics. New York: Dutton.
-
Hiley, B.J. & Peat, F.D. (eds.) (1991). Quantum Implications: Essays
in honour of David Bohm. London and New York: Routledge.
-
Inglis, B. (1984). Science and Parascience: A history of the
paranormal, 1914-1939. London: Hodder and Stoughton.
-
Inglis, B. (1992). Natural and Supernatural: A History of the
Paranormal from the Earliest Times to 1914. Bridport/Lindfield:
Prism/Unity. First published in 1977.
-
Jahn, R.G. & Dunne, B.J. (1987). Margins of Reality: The Role of
Consciousness in the Physical World. New York: Harcourt Brace.
-
Laughlin, C.D. (1996). Archetypes, Neurognosis and the Quantum Sea.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, 10:3, 375.
-
Milton, R. (1994). Forbidden Science: Suppressed research that could
change our lives. London: Fourth Estate.
-
Mitchell, E. with Williams, D. (1996). The Way of the Explorer: An
Apollo Astronaut’s Journey Through the Material and Mystical Worlds.
New York: Putnam.
-
Pagels, H.R. (1983). The Cosmic Code: Quantum Physics as the
Language of Nature. New York: Bantam.
-
Purucker, G. de (1973). The Esoteric Tradition. Pasadena,
California: Theosophical University Press. 2nd ed. first published
in 1940.
-
Sheldrake, R. (1989). The Presence of the Past: Morphic Resonance
and the Habits of Nature. New York: Vintage.
-
Sperry, R.W. (1994). Holding Course Amid Shifting Paradigms. In New
Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Science, edited by W. Harman with
J. Clark. Sausalito, California: Institute of Noetic Sciences.
-
Talbot, M. (1992). The Holographic Universe. New York:
HarperPerennial.
-
Thornton, M. (1989). Do we have free will? Bristol: Bristol
Classical Press.
-
Tiller, W.A. (1993). What Are Subtle Energies? Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 7:3, 293.
-
Weber, R. (1990). Dialogues with Scientists and Sages: The Search
for Unity. London: Arkana.
|